PARTICULARISM AND RESULTANCE

 

Moral particularism is a promising new approach which understands itself as a subchapter of holism in the theory of reasons. So particularism may be extended to other areas, such as metaphysics. One of the bases for this kind of move is elaborated by particularism itself as resultance, a strategy for providing the relevant basis that is opposed to various forms of generalism (the thin property of goodness is constituted by several thick properties, such as being good humoured, being pleasant; the property of this being a table is constituted from properties of there being four legs, a plate, a certain arrangement). It is claimed that resultance or emergence needs a background structure in order to get off the ground.

 

Moral particularism

Moral particularism is an important new approach. The field of ethics and of moral philosophy have undergone dramatic changes because of it. Ross and Moore get widely discussed. There are books on particularism (Little-Hooker 2000) and by particularists (Dancy 1993, 2000, forthcoming 2004).

            What is moral particularism? It is a view that there are no general moral principles guiding our actions, and that moral action is based upon the insight into singular non-repeatable cases. Moral decisions are lead by the normative authority of the particular, and not by the normative authority of the general. Such a view is in disaccord with the usual opinion according to which moral life and education has to be grounded upon moral principles.

            One main idea leading to particularism is that there are several ways of organizing an area: that of the exceptionless general rules, that of generalities which allow for exceptions such as ceteris paribus clauses, and that of the singular cases whose list cannot be subsumed under any general principles. Dancy’s moral particularism is a byproduct of an endeavor starting in the area of causality. The main idea there was that causality cannot be treated in atomistic manner coming under jurisdiction of general exceptionless laws. The approach was eventually elaborated for the area of morality.

            An important ingredient of particularism is that of the patterns that get involved into it. Generalists think that the only metaphysically feasible and explanatory plausible items are general patterns, which act as subsumptive devices.[1] Particularist will point out the importance of singular patterns, i.e. of the patterns characteristic for each single case, whose validity cannot be generally extended. And, if it gets extended, then this is rather the matter of a cosmic accident upon the canvass of the picture governed by the paint of the singular.

 

Monism and pluralism; generalism and particularism

In order to see how it is possible to have a plausible view avoiding general patterns as decisive items, it is instructive to have a look at generalist strategies of monism and pluralism. Monism claims that just one general principle organizes the area of morality, such as this is for example the principle of utility in the view of the utilitarian. But besides to other flaws of such a position, it is not clear how moral conflict would be possible under it: if there is just one principle governing all of our moral decisions, why would one come into the situation of indecision and of conflict?

            Moral pluralism takes care of cases of the now mentioned sort, affirming that there exists plurality of moral principles and not just one. Sartre’s case of a young man is usually mentioned, who has to decide between the duties of fighting Germans in the occupied France, or of helping his old mother. There are two duties in conflict here, one of the patriotic kind, and another involving respect for aging parents. There is a room for a genuine conflict of duties. The conflict has to be approached with insightful judgment encompassing the overall situation. Another example figures yourself driving to an important meeting where you firmly promised somebody to take part. While driving there, you encounter a person involved into an accident, yourself being the only person around who is able to provide the necessary help. You are thus torn between the duties of keeping your promise, and of  helping the person in need. Again, you have to decide on the basis of your involved intuitions. If you decide to help the person in need, you may feel regret, according to the pluralist approach. This regret will be felt because one principle (that of keeping the promises, in the discussed case) was not silenced, but was only temporally put out of voice. There is plenty space for genuine regret in particularism. So particularist will also have to account for regret felt in the described case. But the regret will then not be related to the breaching of general moral principles. Rather, it will be related to the impossibility to take account of all the morally relevant properties and tendencies in a certain particular case, and to such sources as that a certain action has failed to fit into the track of one’s style of living. Particularist will thrive on intuitions, but not on intuitions that would involve clash of principles. Rather, there will be the intuition based on singular and unique patterns of each involved case. Perhaps one can say that particularist will follow the tendencies of the relevant and not of the principled regret.

 

Atomism and holism

Atomism claims how in considering a decision to undertake an action, such as a moral action, one has to take care of a single feature, without considering its embedding into the context in which it appears. It is then a natural suggestion that the support of such a single feature will be measured by tractable and possibly exceptionless procedures and by principles under which it falls.

            Holism, on the other hand, understands a feature as primarily coming embedded into a complex contextual setting, in the framework of which only it is capable to exercise its influence. The contribution of a feature to the overall situation will then not possibly be measured by tractable means and exceptionless principles. Rather, the insight into the overall situation will be of primary importance. Holism offers a natural environment for particularist deliberation, whereas atomism lies close to generalist techniques.

 

A wider look at particularism: although particularism is formulated for the area of morality, it may be extended to other areas, such as metaphysics. This extension of particularism is a natural follow-up to the self-understanding of particularism as a subchapter of holism in the theory of reasons

Particularism was mainly formulated in the area of morality up to date. But the teaching of primacy of normative authority for particular cases does not need to be restricted to the area of morality. It is at least logically possible that particularism may be elaborated for other areas such as metaphysics, say, or for the area of epistemology.[2] Of course the specificity of each of these areas should be then taken into account. Dancy himself, as the main proponent of moral particularism, started his deliberation in the area of causality, his first intuition being that causality cannot be appropriately accounted for by the atomistic approach: causes rather have to be portrayed in a holistic manner, without any general exceptionless or even general principles with exceptions being involved into specifying them. And accordingly, Dancy is sympathetic or at least he is not contrary to the extension of particularist approach to other areas.

            More generally, Dancy also understands moral particularism as a subchapter of a wider approach of holism in the theory of reasons. So reasons for action, and not just moral reasons, are to be handled in a holistic manner. But this then invites the thought that other areas may be approached in a holistic or in a particularist manner as well.

 

Resultance: a strategy for providing a relevant basis that is opposed to various forms of generalism

One important area in the particularist approach involves resultance, the feature that accounts for the relation between moral properties and between the basis upon which these moral properties get grounded.

            But the idea of resultance is rather wider and it extends way beyond the cases of morality. Where does the property of this cliff being dangerous come from? It is grounded upon properties of its being slippery and of its fragility. Where is the property of this entity being a table actually grounded? It is based upon such properties as there being four legs, a plate here, and a certain structural arrangement of these. The property table results from or is constituted by these grounding properties. It is not difficult to see that grounding properties may themselves be further branched into sub-grounding properties, such as the property of the plate resulting on properties of this material, of certain rigidity. The property of this act being good results from its grounding properties of being well-minded, of being humble, of happening or being acted at the appropriate time and place.

            The relation of resultance is appropriate for a particularist in that it does not appeal to any general principles. The grounding relation is not guided by any generalities that would contribute to the result of goodness, say. Goodness is a thin property (thin, because it does not have a lot of content characterizing it). A generalist will suppose that thick properties (that of being well-minded, humble) always come with the same polarity. This is countered by a particularist, who opposes the tendency to see thick properties as instrumental only in respect to thin moral properties. The particularist will try to relieve the stress from thin properties, by emphasizing the shape brought in by the holistic environment of intertwined thick properties and of the project of somebody’s own itinerary.

            Resultance provides the possibility of delivering a particularist account of grounding relation, which enables to argue against various forms of generalism. Generalist approaches do not just come in the shape of monism, but mostly in various forms of Rossian pluralism. They all try to claim that a feature has the same contributory weight in all the diversity of circumstances: if they have the positive weight in this case, say, they will have to retain the same weight in all the subsequent cases. Generalists will also tend to allow for ceteris paribus soft laws and thus for exceptions, as long as the normative authority of the general will remain unshattered.

            Resultance provides one basis for battling all these sorts of generalism. Resultance does not get the relevance of features from the general rules being involved into these. Resultance grounding somehow provides the relevance for free. Well, not entirely for free, as we will try to indicate later on; there will be a non-classical structure involved into the endeavor of its shape.

            As far as the grounding relation is concerned, resultance provides a basis that is quite different to that of supervenience. Supervenience is the grounding relation account from the side of the generalist strategy.[3]

 

Humean argument that there can be no goodness besides to the thick good properties, that there can be no mind besides to the thick mental properties. Implausibility of this: compare: "there can be no table besides to the thick properties of there being four legs, of there being a plate, of there being a certain arrangement of these parts. You can perceive just these thick poroperties, whereas table is nothing but an idea in your mind". This last argument is clearly not plausible, and the reasoning may be extended back to the implausibility of other Humean arguments. So, resultance or emergence is possible (but as we will see emergence still needs a relevance encompassing structure in order to be able to get off the ground).

There is a consideration in the direction that relevance cannot even get off the ground. This is a Humean consideration spreading skepticism over the very possibility of properties resulting upon a diversified base. The strategy is skeptical as to the transition from thick to the thin properties, and in this sense would have to be close to some particularist efforts to relieve the stress off the thin properties.[4] But again, as already claimed, it is established first of all in order to argue against the very possibility of resultant relations.

            A Humean may say that there is no property of goodness besides to the thick good properties of benevolece and of helpfulness, in a certain case. Or that there is no property figuring the self besides to the various thick mental properties. Wherever you will look in your mind, you will only find some thoghts, or impressions, or again conscious events, but no self. In the same sense you will find just thick moral properties of benevolence and non-selfishness but no thin property of goodness besides to these.

            The arguing in this direction may be easily shown as not appropriate on the basis of the following consideration. There are these thick properties of there being four legs, of there being a plate, of there being a certain arrangement. But there is no property of the table resulting from these. The property of table would be just something that we inappropriately construe in our minds. This reasoning seems utterly implausible, as everyone easily sees that there is a table there. And so there are good deeds and minds.

            This establishes that resultance or emergence is possible. I.e., emergent properties of goodness or of table may be accounted for. But just how are they accounted for and just what brings their relevance into the picture is another matter. It relates to the question of the structure supporting the emergentist relevance.

 

Resultance as following particularist unique patterns (beautiful patterns) as opposed to the generalist strategy of supervenience. "Because" as an important characterization of relevance. Did you help this person in this case because of the general principle prescribing such a help to you? The answer rather seems that you helped her because of a rich variety of properties and characteristics involved into the particular situation. This richness and dynamics of the forces involved into the situation was the reason for you helping her, and not any general principles.

Resultance is distinguished against generalist strategies in that it does not claim how the resultant property, in order to come about, would need any general patterns. The resultance rather builds on unique singularly shaped patterns, which may be called beautiful patterns in respect to the aesthetic pattern structures that support the beauty of works of art. As opposed to this, supervenience is the generalist strategy accounting for grounding relation, which will be more closely dealt with in the following section.

            One way to account for the resultance is the characterization of “because” involved into it. Did[5] you help this person now because of the general principle underlying your activity? This may be what you claim. I.e., in providing the reason for your action you will use the appeal to general principles: “I helped her because one always needs to help people in need”. But you obviously do not help all the people in need around the world during all the time. This would change your life profoundly and it would not be feasible. You used the appeal to the general principle because of the epistemic handiness it is dued with. In fact, your reasons to help her in the situation that we are discussing were much more diversified, depending both on the multiplicity of factors inolved and on your ability of quickly discerning and deciding in which way it is proper to engage in one’s actions. The richness and dynamics of the forces involved into the situation was the real reason for your activity of helping her, and not any general principles, to which you may appeal in an epistemic manner.

 

The implausibility of the supervenient project: it is possible to construe a generalist supervenient pattern just on the basis of implausible holistically exact match of two situations. Objections to this strategy: The doubling of twin situations is rather a cosmic accident (the utter improbability to have two exactly similar St. Francis Twins). Supervenient relation tries to bring in the guarantee for the general pattern to come through, without considering anything else. But there is no relevance. Supervenient generalist strategy is introduced by counterfactual lawlikeness.

Supervenient grounding strategy opposes the resultance based or emergentist grounding strategy. What does supervenience do? Certainly it is an account of grounding relation. Supervenience will try to explain, as for that matter, how the property of goodness will be grounded on a certain underlying basis.

            The generality of supervenient tactics may be seen because of its basic appeal to general principles or to general laws, which are brought in by considering counterfactual situations. Counterfactuals all by themselves support generalizations by securing law-like connections. There are counterfactual lawful generalizations.

            Take an example of supervenient relation. There is St.Francis, and he is a good person. The property of St.Francis being good supervenes upon his property of being humble, of his helping the people at appropriate times and places. But this is not enough to establish a supervenient relation. Supervenient relation needs a guarantee of the generalist sort. This is why one introduces St.Francis twin, with exaclty the same properties in its subvenient thick basis as the original St.Francis. And here comes the main generalist induced claim concerning counterfactuals and determining the supervenient property of goodness. If St.Franics is good, and if there would be this St.Francis twin, wih the same subvenient physical and thick moral properties as these that are found in the original St.Francis, then St.Francis twin cannot fail to be good as well. This is to say that the property of goodness supervenes on both occasions. But this is then also determining the supervenient property of goodness itself, deriving it from the generalist pattern according to which it is supposed to proceed.[6]

            But consider now that all this supervenient construction was actually made because of the wish to deliver a generalist account of the situation. Just a moment’s thought will reveal to you that the whole construction established in view of providing a guarantee of the general was there just for this matter: to secure a generalist lawful relation in order to support the supervenient property of goodness. Waiving that, it must seem utterly implausible to have the situation of identical St.Francis twins in the world. Could not already the original St.Francis be considered as being good, without these generality lawful involving considerations introducing supervenient properties? It is actually a probability of accidence involving cosmic proportions to find two exactly similar situations. But the adherent of supervenience has gone to big troubles in order to secure such an unlikely case – obviously just in order to claim that the property of goodness will have some authority only if it is established upon some generalist pattern. But this presupposition (that there are general patterns needed in order to act morally, say) is in no way to be taken for granted. The particularist will claim just to the contrary that there aren’t any generalities involved into a deed being good. It really depends on this particular situation. Each feature may change its valence from one situation to another one, from one context to another. There is no need for any general pattern of this kind as the basis for having good acts, from the side of particularist.

            So this entire generalist supervenient grounding strategy heads into a wrong, unrealistic and implausible direction. Once one realizes this, the strategy proposed by resultance seems to be a much more plausible alternative for an account of grounding relation. There is no necessity for the appeal to the general rules. All that which is needed is just the reliance of particularist unique and interestingly shaped patterns involved into each particular context.

 

Resultance is emergence: the basis thrives just upon the relevant properties, not upon all of the properties as this is the case for supervenience. There is no relevance in the supervenient basis.

Resultance is actually emergence, as this was already hinted at. Dancy himslef called the relation emergence, but he was persuaded to give up the offensive title, offensive at least in the mind of his publisher, for resultance. Again, one should consider that there is some history to the term of resultance. Ross spoke about toti-resultant and parti-resultant properties, toti-resultance dependning on the whole situation, and parti-resultance being grounded just in a part of the relevant context.

            Abolishing the recourse to any general patterns enables one to establish the grounding resultance basis upon the relevant properties exclusivelly, and not indiscriminately in its dependency upon all the properties, as this was the case for supervenient counterfactual relation.

            There cannot be any relevance in the subvenient basis, because all the physical and all the thick properties are included into it. But relevance certainly needs some considerations of salience, which are not provided by generalist supervenient strategies.

            It is a great idea to have such a relevant basis with resultance. But it will not come without some support of the particular pattern involved into it, the pattern that is able to provide relevance without any appeal to generality. Patterns involved into works of art (pattern of this painting, pattern involved into the complex Don Juan opera) are the cases in point. I think that Dancy should show the way towards such patterns in order to be able to explain how relevance is capable coming off the ground.

 

Dancy's way of posing the dilemma: (1) Either there is generalism and atomism, general principles and rule governed practices. (2) Or there is emergence, the relevant properties. In this last case it is the matter of skills how to discriminate properties. Comparison with the generalist semantics: there is no core meaning of conjunction for the word "and"; the skill of discriminating the semantic contribution of the word in varying situations is needed.

Dancy seems to see the general dilemma involving particularism against the generalism consideration just in the follwing way: either one goes with generalism or one goes with particularism. But this is too short. There has to be a middle way of a sort between these, and there needs to be some structure and some underlying basis, a pattern that is not a generalist pattern. Dancy is too reluctant to recognize such a structure, and so he fails to provide an appropriate account of the particularist basis. Yet recently he has enabled a move in this direction by opting for defaults and similar devices that should provide some structure without that this would need to be an ultimately generalistically based structure. One way to go here is obvious. There are default values of cruel deeds say, which may turn out to be mostly wrong. But such a default may be seen as an epistemic feature. So the default being just an epistemic generality cannot really be a metaphysically grounded generality.[7]

            A much more straightforward way is to recognize the possibility of unique and nonrepeatable patterns, such as various aesthetic patterns involved into works of art. This is the possibility that does not seem to be recognizied to a sufficient extent by Dancy in building a metaphysical underlying basis for his particularism.

            Dancy seems rather to argue in the following way:

 

(1)   Either there is generalism and atomism, general principles and rule governed practices.

(2)   Or, there is particularism, emergence or resultance and relevant properties.

 

As he is pointing to (2), Dancy depicts the matter of reaching the goodness of acts, say, as being that of skills that are there in order to discriminate the properties in a certain context.

            But reference to skills somehow has the undertone of there being no structure, as opposed to the generalist well entrenched structure, proceeding over general patterns.

            So, Dancy seems to miss the possibility of there being a structure that is not a generalist structure. He does argue in this direction to some extent in his seminal particularist semantic sketch. The meaning of the world “and” does not have a core of conjunction, according to this approach. There is no such core, rather the matter of mastering the meaning of the word “and” depends on the skilfull discriminating contribution of the word in the contexts in which it always appears, such as in: “And what do you think you are doing?”

            The opposition of full generalist patterns supported rules and between the no rules but skills based practical discriminatory ability is just too simplistic. There must be a more refined possibility out there in the logical space: a relevance providing structure without generality.

 

Helping Dancy: providing him a way out about relevance. A structure is needed. What kind of structure? We can go along with Dancy in acknowledging that it is wrong to suppose just the existence of generalist repeatable patterns. There are also the unique beautiful patterns. These are interesting patterns, they bear relevance upon their sleeve: aesthetic patterns (the Gestalt pattern of Don Juan opera, of Vltava symphony, of this picture as a work of art): they do not repeat themselves, they are not included into any generalist pattern, but it is because of this that they are the bearers of relevance. There is no relevance because of the generalist patterns! And there is nothing more relevant than works of art. They give direction to your life, if something does.

Let me come again to the relevant patterns. These are patterns, obviously, not just skilfull things without any real underlying structure. Skills should be underpinned with some structure as well. Generative grammar for example is understood as an underlying rich structure to linguistic skills. So in any way, an account of the structure underlying skills is still needed.

            A positive account of particularism, not just arguing against various forms of genralism, is needed as well. Phenomenology involved into action and into deliberating of action seems to offer an obvious example. Delivering a viable example of non-generalist but relevance providing structure is another one.

            Aesthetic works of art seem to provide the desired patterns. Interesting aesthetic patterns bear the relevance upon their sleeve. Think on the unique and complex patterns underlying Don Juan opera, or again on the patterns of Vltava symphony or again on those involved into paintings in the gallery. All of these works of art are unique. They do not repeat themselves. They are not included into any generalist pattern. If somebody would write another Don Juan this would be just considered as a plagiat or as some bloodless repetition of the primary powerful and not to be repeated original.

            On the other hand, aesthetic works of art certainly seem to offer the prototype for bearers of relevance. There is not any relevance in the works of art because of the generalist patterns that may be involved into them. Even epistemic appeals to the generalist supported relevance on their basis are more than dubious. But again, there does not seem to be anything as relevant as the works of art. They may give a direction to your life, they may help you in finding an unique path of your particular journey.

 

The case of relevant properties in resultance: thin property of goodness is constituted by several thick properties, such as that of being good-humoured, being pleasant. The property of this being a table is constituted by several thick properties, such as there being four legs, a plate, there being a certain arrangement.

Generalist sees thick properties, such as these of being good humoured, being pleasant, as always relevant and as relevant in the same manner at all occasions of its appearance. Particularism, as already mentioned, will try to see thick properties not as instrumental in obtaining the thin property, and as retaining their valence through all occasions. It will rather see the thin property as not being of any big importance. The reasons for action, say, will come from the pattern of thick properties from such a particularist perspective, being guided by the zero-level of itinerary, which may be described somehow as the way of someone’s particular itinerary, the way someone actually leads one’s life. There may be nothing dramatic in the way you live your life, but it will still be a manner, a certain way in which you do live it. Some input of art will certainly be able to provide a special quality to the way of your living your life. The thin property is somehow not different from the thick properties that constitute it; rather, it is identical to their arrangement.

 

Helping Dancy: what is needed is something to support the emergentist structure of resultance basis. What is thus needed here? A background structure!

The way of helping Dancy is to supply something that will support the relevance. The needed thing is the background structure. Emergence is not enough. Emergence will not provide relevance by itself. A background structure will be able to do this. One way to characterize this background structure is by invoking the background, such as it was mentioned by Searle as he discussed intentionality. Background is not the outright intentionality; it is the structure establishing the preconditions of intentionality in an indirect way.

 

Example of background underlying structure: morphological content. It is wrong to think that there are just (1) general exceptionless rules, or (2) skillfully accountable particular cases with no structure at all (compare Fodor vs. Dreyfus). The logical space of possibilities needs to be extended. There is a structure, which provides the relevance, the intractable background rich structure, such as that of morphological content. It is wrong to think that resultance/emergence does not need any structure. Example of background structure for the case of morphological content: a rich multi-dimensional landscape that operates without rules but that provides relevance with the settling up of states into local minima. Emergence may not have and does need an additional structure indeed, but this will not be structure based upon general exceptionless rules.

Another way to provide background structure is by invoking morphological content in the area of cognition supporting the non-classical picture of models of mind. Morphological content presents an example of beautiful pattern, i.e. of a pattern that does not follow the requirements of generality in order to achieve relevance. Classical models allow for three levels of description: a cognitive system may be described at the levels of implementation, of algorithm and of cognitive function. The description of implementation basically encompasses physically realized hardware. Cognitive function centers at whatever is outright displayed by the cognitive system, what may be interpreted as total cognitive states such as beliefs or desires. Whereas the description at the level of algorithm tries to capture the conditions for whatever is displayed at the top level.

            According to Marr’s classical description, we find an algorithm at the cognitive system’s middle level. This means that a kind of tractable procedure such as specified by some algorithm assures the conditions for whatever appears at the top level of cognitive system’s description. The conditions for this occurrent belief of mine to appear are given by a tractable algorithm that may be specified, even if the pattern it supports is a complex one, probabilistic or if it harbors some other kind of diversity. The idea behind the algorithmic approach is that even for such complex cases a tractable algorithm may be found that specifies their general repeatable patterns as the conditions for what is displayed by the cognitive system at its top level.

            Horgan and Tienson (1996) propose a substantial qualitative extension of levels involved into the description of cognitive systems. The basic move happens at the middle level of cognitive system’s description[8], where “mathematical-state transitions”[9] substitute the classical algorithm. What is going on here? The extended generic model is inspired by connectionist models of mind, as opposed to the classical language of thought based models of mind. Connectionist systems proposed an architecture that is not based upon classical algorithms, but rather upon dynamical mathematics inspired procedures. A rich multi-dimensional landscape that operates without rules but that provides relevance with the settling up of the system’s states into local minima underlies the endeavor. By this move, connectionism certainly has shown the way out of the classical architecture. But just adopting connectionist mathematical-state transitions would be too short if the aim is providing a description adequate to the performance of the actual cognitive systems. It would be too short if connectionist inspired description would still retain as its departure some tractable procedures, of a probabilistic or some similar kind. And it would be too short if any claim in favor of the structure would be abandoned and if one would give free course to a kind of computational anarchy. Connectionism is just inspiration and entrance into deciphering of a non-classical relevance providing structure, into a non-classical language of thought. The support for such a structure comes at the middle level of the non-classical or generic description as the structure of morphological content that supports mathematical-state transitions. Without morphological content, these transitions just are not relevant. In connectionist models of mind, as opposed to the classical models of mind, the outcome gets determined by its’ positioning in the multi-dimensional mathematical space and not by any algorithm.

            What is morphological content thus? It is the background content or background structure at the middle level of non-classical generic cognitive system’s description, a structure that may not be described by any tractable means, but that provides relevance or in other words condition for whatever appears at the top level of cognitive system’s description. Morphological systems may be described as an intractable background landscape that provides the points for positioning of top total cognitive states and that determines cognitive-state transitions. The structure of the cognitive system at this middle level of description is intractable but relevant for determining whatever appears at the higher computational level. The relevance has to be obtained by something. Morphological content does not provide relevance by repeatable or tractable general patterns but by its holistic intractable unique structure. Notice, by the way, that this unique particular structure is not static, but that it traces the relevant points of positioning through time. This means that the relevance tracking structure itself is substantially dynamic. Morphological content as the background structure gets displayed at such occasions, as is the one where my specific intonation accompanies my pronouncing of the English text, myself being brought up as a speaker of Slovene language. More simply and obviously, morphological content is active in positioning of anything that gets occurrently displayed by my cognitive system: my thoughts, the things I say, the acts I perform. The background structure determines all of these and most of them are relevant for situations and activities I get involved in. For each singular case, there is this dynamical relevant structure. Morphological structure provides singular beautiful but dynamically changing and adjusting pattern.

            While discussing situation in the area of models of mind, Horgan and Tienson (1996) assert the need for a broader picture out there as just the one described either by exceptionless general rules based models of mind on the one hand, such as Fodors’s classical language of thought model, and between the connectionist models based conceptions of mind, such as the ones promoted by skills (Dreyfus) and with absence of general structure (Churchlands). There is a range of possibilites, which may be inspired by connectionism, but which do not reject all forms of structure along with the rejection of the generalist based structure. Such a possibility involves what Horgan and Tienson call the model of dynamical cognition. Dynamical cognition leans heavily on the idea of rich background virtual space that shapes in many directions the way our cognition goes. This virtual multi-dimensional space includes morphological content, which is not occurrent content, but rather whatever is involved into the weights, if one may use connectionism inspired terminology. Morphological content comes from the underlying structure that shapes the direction of the forms of cognition to occurr.

            In classical computational models, whatever appears at the occurrent level of the system gets determined by the underlying exceptionless structure or algorithm, by a language of thought. Dynamical cognition, to the contrary, builds upon unique singular beautiful patterns.  These patterns still provide a language of thought, but a non-classical one. This is a dynamics based language of thought without algorithms.

            Resultance or emergence needs an underlying structure in order to have relevance embedded into it. If such a structure as is the one brought by the morphological content is provided, then we can escape the simplistic opposition between just (1) general exceptionless rules on the one hand and between the (2) skillfully accountable particular cases with no structure at all on the other hand. This would then be similar as the opposition between Fodor and Dreyus in the area of models of mind (general exceptionless atomistic rules as against skills that are nor based on any structure, the no-structure here being understood as skills). The logical space of possibilities has to be extended in respect to these. There is a structure that provides the relevance, the intractable background rich structure, such as the structure proper to the morphological content. Resultance or emergence does need some structure indeed in order to be able to produce relevance. The background structure of the morphological content may provide a guidance here. Morphological content involves a rich multi-dimensional landscape that operates without rules and provides relevance with the settling up of virtual states into local minima. Emergence does not have and it needs a structure indeed, but this will not be a structure that involves general exceptionless rules.

 

Relevance and the frame problem (a robot will not be able to act because of the impossibility to get around on the basis of tractable rules). The action iself is possible upon the rich and dynamical background of contributing and enabling conditions as reasons for action, based on facts and context and not on beliefs and desires (The reason for me to having helped her is the fact that she needs help, not my belief in this direction; ultimately the fact as a reason may have some weight in the context only).

One example illustrating relevance involves the frame problem. Dennett describes a robot with a bomb attached to it that will explode in a due time. Robot is also equipped with a powerful classical computer based on rule governed symbol crunching and with input devices of visual and other appropriate sorts. The task of the robot is evidently that of recognizing that there is a bomb attached to it, that it is in danger and that it has to act accordingly so that it can escape the dangerous fate. The lesson of the frame problem is that there are no chances for the robot to be successful if it follows the elaboration of the input information according to the classical rule governed symbol-crunching computer. The robot will look at you, it will elaborate the information related to your eyes, to the color of your shirt. Well before it will be able to realize that it might be in danger it will be too latte for it to undertake any action for saving itself. The reason is that tractable rules will not by themselves assure any relevance.

            The action does not follow tractable computing crunching, but it is rather possible upon the background of rich and dynamical contributing and enabling conditions that figure as reasons for action.

            Dancy has criticized the view that mental states, such as desires or beliefs, may figure as the relevant reasons for action. If some of these would be able to figure as reasons, then this would be beliefs because of their bigger amount of objectivity as compared to the desires preferred by Humeans. But facts are even more objective. I helped her not because I believed that I need to help her; the real good reason for my action is the fact that she was in need, not my belief to this effect. But there is something that is even more objective than the fact: it is the rich context that provides an appropriate reason for my action of helping her.

 

The structure of resultance

The dilemma for the particularist profiled itself in the following terms: either on the one hand there are generalities that are responsible for moral or for other higher order properties, or on the other hand there is just skilful underpinning of particular cases. What are the skills we are talking about? One area for skills is our mastering of language. What conditions are needed in order for someone to understand a certain word? The meaning of a word is not mastered by elaborating upon some kind of its core meaning, but by appropriately handling the usage of the word in various contextual settings. The meaning of the word “and” does not equal some general semantic core meaning such as conjunction. For there are other forms of the usage of “and”, such as it appears in the sentence “And what do you think you are doing?” If one agrees not to buy generalities and if one embraces skills, there is still the question about the structure that conveys relevance. Up till now we have not presupposed any background structure to be involved into the skillful handling of cases. But such a structure may perhaps be found if we look at the ways in which resultance itself is shaped.

            The following schema may be construed along the lines of Dancy’s (1993) presentation of resultance:

 

0 – 0 -0

0 I 0 o        -constituency→   thin moral property

 

thick moral properties

 

Ý resultance

 

natural properties

 

A structure providing relevance may be found at two stages of the schema. These stages have different tasks to fulfill. But taken together they also constitute an account of a unique phenomenon. Schema may be illustrated by substituting “good” for the thin moral property, “benevolence”, “friendliness”, “helpfulness” for thick moral properties and whatever physical material and other properties underlie these for natural properties. The goodness of my act is constituted by its benevolence, friendliness and helpfulness, as well as by the ways in which these are distributed in the context of moral situation. These thick properties and their arrangement though result from the involved natural properties.

            There are two relations involved into the phenomenon in its entirety. The first is the relation of resultance. The second relation of constituency does not proceed between two levels; it rather succeeds at one single level. There are no generalities involved into these relations at any of the involved stages.

            The relation of resultance is that between natural properties and between thick properties. The additional relation of constituency succeeds between thick properties and between the thin property. If there is thin property of being good, it is constituted by thick properties of benevolence, of temperance, of efficacy, of friendliness and by the shape of a certain situation in which these thick properties appear. Constituency is not a mediating kind of relation. The thick properties involved, such as friendliness and efficacy, together with their overall shape in a certain case do not really appear at another level, as is the level of the thin property that they constitute. Thick properties and their arrangement are in fact the resulting thin relation. There is nothing else as these thin properties and their arrangement or their form that would constitute the thin property of goodness – in this particular case.

            But thick properties, such as friendliness and benevolence, result from other properties. So there is a more indirect relation in the case of resultance as there is in the case of constituency. Thick properties are grounded in and they result from natural properties. But there are several layers of resultant properties involved into the overall relation of resultance. The thick property of efficacy, for example, results upon several properties such as keeping promises, doing appropriate things, which again result from other properties underlying them. Finally, at some stage, the resultant tree of such properties reaches the natural basis. While there is such a resultant tree for the relation of resultance, there is nothing comparable for constitution: thick properties simply constitute the thin property. Thick properties and their overall arrangement in a certain situation together just are the thin property. In the area of artifacts, the table as the thin property gets constituted from thick properties of there being four legs, of there being a plate and certain arrangement in which these fit together. Table is nothing else as the appropriate arrangement of these thick properties. But thin properties result from a tree arrangement of their underlying thick properties (the table plate results from this material of a certain density) and ultimately from their underlying natural properties. The table is constituted by all of these.

            Considering these two stages of the phenomenon in its entirety, we may see that there is a structure providing relevance involved into both of them. There is the structure of the resultance tree and there is the structure of constitution. So we are not just talking about the absence of structure, meaning thereby the absence of a general structure in the case of resultance. To the contrary, resultance introduces a rich and powerful underlying structure conveying relevance to whatever emerges as its product.

            Perhaps the phenomenon of bringing resultance and constituency together repeats itself at several intermediate stages of the resultance tree. Resultance tree is where thick properties result from several underlying properties. The beginning of the branching is at the level of the natural properties. But resultance tree usually contains a lot of properties that are of higher level, as are the natural physical properties. So it is possible to consider relation of constituency appearing already at the level where the resultance operates. 

            We now wish to take a slightly closer look at the relation of constituency. The question is about the kind of basis upon which the thin property gets constituted. There are two candidate possibilities:

 

(a)    thick properties –constitution→ thin moral property

(b)   thick properties + their form –constitution→ thin moral property

 

A particularist will go for (b), which corresponds to the above schema figuring resultance. If he would go for (a), he would finish with kind of type-type constitution theory. This would claim that a certain type of thick properties is bound to constitute a certain type of thin property. The adherence to the type would bring generalities into the picture. But because of the variable and intractable richness of the thick properties available to support the thin property of goodness, say, it is questionable whether any such general type would be forthcoming. It is also questionable to talk about the thin moral property as about a type, because there is just one such property available, goodness in our case. And because there will be no inherent form of the constitution involved in (a), this proposal will be atomistic and thus it will lack holism as the distinguishing mark of the particularist approach. This would also not be compatible with the main claims of particularistic holism, because types involve generalities: a certain kind of type has general and lawfully predictable consequences for several cases. We then finish in an atomistic kind of constitution relation – according to atomism a feature or a certain set of features has the same consequences without respect to the situation involved – which is incompatible with particularist holism.[10]

            If we embrace the possibility (b) though, the relation of constitution will be that of token-token identity. This is a more natural move for a particularist. The form or shape of thick properties coming together that is to be found in this case makes for all the difference. We are talking about a holistic form, in the sense in which a particularist understands holism. This means that there are these thick properties. But as there is also the landscape together with its shape in which these properties appear, their valence may change along with the altering of landscape’s form. One such example would figure Dancy’s story about his young daughter stepping on a sea urchin. The extraction of the urchin’s needle caused pain, and causing pain is not a good making property. But because of the overall situation in which this feature appeared, i.e. because of the shape into which the thick properties came in this case, the contribution and the valence of the feature changed. The addition of the form to the assemblage of thick properties in (b) thus exercises holistic effect – the claim that the valence of a feature may change in respect to the form of the involved context. This makes the approach in (b) compatible with token-token identity theory. Token-token identity namely does not commit itself to the generality of types, it just claims in favor of a support that may be different for each particular case involved. This also accords with the observation that there is an immense variability and richness of thick properties underlying a certain thin property. There is a practically infinite number of thick property bases for a certain thin property such as goodness, with each of the thick characteristics involved being capable of changing its valence in respect to the holistic form of context in which it appears as the support for a given thin property. We cannot construe any generalities in respect to how these relations get linked between themselves. Now it is obvious why the form or the shape in (b) is important in order that the approach can have a particularist touch to it.

            A distinguishing characteristic of the model according to (b) is that the form or the overall shape pertaining to a certain case gets involved into it. Because of the adherence of the form to the particular case no general predictions about how one may compute by tractable means the result of several thick properties coming together at a certain landscape may be made. We have to do with particular and not with general patterns.[11] This is also why there are no definitions really available about how to realize necessary and sufficient conditions for good properties. The resultant property just emerges upon a rich background that cannot be mastered by tractable means. Such a resultant property[12] brings the emergence based upon the particular pattern along with it. There will be relevance achieved upon the form of such intractable basis. And it will not be generalistically justifiable relevance but a particularist relevance, i.e. the relevance achieved on the basis of particularly shaped patterns. It now becomes doubtful whether relevance may be achieved upon an underlying set of properties, without inherently coming in the shape of particular unique patterns or forms. In one way, one may talk about the property of goodness as resulting from a natural basis. But it also gets constituted from the thick properties.

            In fact, breaking down of the relation of resultance and emergence has shown us a way out of the too simplistic dilemma concerning a choice between general principles and between the skills that do not involve any structure. The form of thick properties or their overall shape from which a thin property is constituted provides the needed structure. Just that this structure cannot be generalized; it is a particular structure, emerging from each case. This is a good point for one to stress that resultance should not be confused for supervenience. Whereas supervenience builds upon general patterns or general forms, presupposing that only generalities can provide a relevant structure, resultance thrives upon singular patterns. Whereas relevance is inherent to each singular pattern (consider work of art as an example, or your singular way of living your life), the relevance involved into supervenience comes from repetition of a certain general pattern. But it is hard to see how just a repetition of a certain situation would bring relevance with it, except in fallacious ways.

            Generalist will try to argue that relevance is to be achieved just on the basis of the general. There is this thin moral property, such as good. But the thin property of goodness has many instances, for there are many good acts around. But if there are many good properties, they must have something in common – being good as for that matter. But then, there obviously exists a generality or a general mechanism that binds all of these instances. What can a particularist say at this point? He may shift attention to the fact that a powerful illusion is exercised here, a drive to recognize general patterns behind various instances. This drive is fuelled by confusion between the epistemic and between the metaphysical. Perhaps similarity and the general are features of the epistemic assessment of the world. The epistemic assessment, such as conceptual assessment, is driven by reduction of the richness and by recognition of several common traits to a range of cases. But it is not the case that these generalities would have a metaphysical underlying basis. Generalities, from this point of view, are just something that gets projected upon the world, with the means proper to language and thought, but without any real metaphysical support.

Supervenience as a generalist strategy takes all natural properties into account, and it does not mention any structure, such as resultance tree. Once all properties are taken into consideration, it only seems that one can achieve relevance on the basis of the repetition of complete situations. It seems that by this means one may get to the general pattern. But it is questionable that general pattern would lead to relevance.[13] Because of this lack of the structure supporting it in the background, supervenience does not thrive on relevance. For the case of resultance however, the particular shape and the lack of definition leads to non-tractability and to emergence, and therewith to relevance. Resultance recognizes that relevance does not come from a general repeatable structure but from an underling particular structure. [14]

 

Literature

Churchland, Paul (1988). Matter and Consciousness. MIT Press.

Dancy, Jonathan (2000). Practical Reality. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Dancy, Jonathan (1993). Moral Reasons. Oxford: Blackwell.

Dancy, Jonathan (Forthcoming).  Ethics Without Principles.

Dreyfus, Hubert (1979). What Computers Can’t Do. Harper and Row.

Fodor, Jerry (1981). RePresentations: Philosophical Essays on the Foundations of Cognitive Science. MIT Press.

Horgan, Terence and Tienson, John (1996). Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology. MA: MIT Press.

Little, Margaret and Hooker, Brad (2001). Moral Particularism. Oxford: OUP.

Potrč, Matjaž (1999) “Morphological Content”, in Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology,  Acta Analytica 22: 133-149.

Searle, John (1983). Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Verdiglione, Armando (2003). Artisti. Milano: Spirali.



[1] In opposition to generalists, particularists think that general patterns (a) proceed without the real need of any ultimate material hookup (supervenience as a generalist strategy involves counterfactual comparing of several situations, without that any of these would have the natural or physical instantiation secured – physical realization is just an additional and even not necessary assumption in the strategy pertaining to the generalist counterfactual patterns); (b) are not explanatory for the areas in which they are often used, such as the area of morality: morality does not require explanation that is shaped according to the requirements of natural sciences including general laws; in the area of morality a suitable explanation would be that of narrativity, which is more appropriate for handling of particular cases, and gets rooted in non-repeatable but relevant patterns.

                If particularism's metaphysical approach uses resultance or emergence, then this involves natural or physical basis as a more binding presupposition. And then narration seems to be an appropriate explanatory strategy.

[2] Lately, Dancy elaborated a basis for a particularist conception of meaning. His general idea was, as he now remarks, »that there should be an analogue to particularism wherever there is rationality to be found«.

[3] Dancy says in his commentary: »I wonder, at the end, whether it is true that supervenience is the generalist's form of the grounding relation. I know that many people think of supervenience as a relation of 'fixing': the subvenient base, in all its enormity, fixes the supervenient property. I myself don't think that this is the right way to think about supervenience at all, however. I would have thought that the generalist analogue for the grounding relation is more likely to be subsumption.«

[4] There is confusion in the Humean approach between the level of the property of there being a table and between the level of properties such as there being four legs, a plate, their arrangement, that constitute the resulting property of there being a table. The property table does not have the same function as the property of there being four legs. The property of there being four legs contributes to the constitution of the property of there being a table. But all the mentioned thick properties (there being four legs, a plate, their arrangement) also are the property of there being a table, in the sense that they constitute this property.

[5] Dancy's commentary: »The question should not be whether you did help the person because of a principle or because of the properties of the case, but whether the reason why you should have helped her was the principle or the properties. That is to say, I think it unwise to go off into the question what actually motivates people, and better to stick to the explicitly normative question about what grounds the relevant ought.«

[6] It is questionable whether any relevance may be derived upon the mere establishing of generalist patterns. Such a presupposition is widely accepted and nevertheless unfounded. Slightly more about this in what follows. Yet the matter would still  merit a separate treatment. 

[7] As Dancy rightly remarks in his commentary, »To think of something as a default is to think more generally about the way in which it functions in a variety of cases, rather than directly about how it is functioning in some particular case before one.« This is clearly a remark about the constitution. But if deafults are taken epistemically as I propose, they would at least be compatible with particular patterns. These would include relevance in several of its forms of salience and shape, of the contributory, the enabling and the intensifying conditions.

[8] The bottom level of cognitive system's description may stay the same for both classical and extended model. The top level of cognitive system's description introduces cognitive-state transitions instead of more static classical cognitive function.

[9] Horgan, T. and Tienson, J. (1996), p. 45.

[10] Type-type identity is not an unusual proposal in the theory of mind. If it just means something such as that a type of mental property results from the natural, i.e. physical properties, this is a comparatively harmless claim. Still, because of adherence of the type identity theory to generalities it will be difficult to incorporate relevance into it. 

[11] It is essential to grasp that particular patterns are still patterns. I.e. they have relevance embedded into themselves, they have a structure, but they certainly are not any general patterns. So particular patterns prove that at least, not all patterns are general. Besides to this, particular patterns possess relevance, whereas this is not so clear for general patterns. I am enjoying this performance of this symphony now, not some general kind of performance. Works of art are relevant in their singularity. Giving examples helps the teaching, whereas appealing to generalities is much less certain outcome.

[12] One would perhaps be better off if talking about the constituted property. But as the overall phenomenon of resultance incorporates both resultant and constituing stages (these may be separated by analysis only, and not in reality), we may also talk about resultant properties.

[13] Compare general and practical syllogisms. »All people are mortal. Socrates is a man. So Socrates is mortal.« does not automatically have relevance for any specific instance. Whereas »If somebody is hungry, they will eat a cake. Here is a cake. I am hungry. So I eat this cake.« applies to particular cases and brings the relevance along with it. Notice that indexicals appear in this later case.

[14] My thanks in preparing of this paper go to Jonathan Dancy for his discussion at the occasion of his Valencia conference in March 2003, and for the written commentary concerning the present paper.